Skip to content

PII

February 24, 2015

Los Angeles, a city devoid of gutters and drainage, flood carrying away its inhabitants in times of rain, waste heaping up and burying them in times of drought.

Fr. 595

February 23, 2015

A recent interview with sociologist Andrew Cherlin at The Guardian provides reason for reflection on the conception of self in contemporary society. Although Cherlin lends his attention to the transformations in the American working class, childbearing and marriage, he briefly evokes a related problem, though familiar to us here:

How can the movement from the “utilitarian self” to the “expressive self” explain the marriage gap?

People talk a lot about American individualism. In the old days it meant working hard, striking out on one’s own, succeeding in your career. Today it often means striving for personal growth, individual development, a happier sense of self. That change occurred among the middle class a few decades ago. It’s now occurring among the working class. We’re now seeing young working-class men and women talk about their lives in the same kind of therapeutic personal-satisfaction sense that the middle class has been showing for decades.

One can say that thinking about one’s personal development is a luxury that could only happen when one’s economic life is in good shape. That’s what happened with the middle class. What’s surprising is that we see the shift to the ‘expressive self’ among the working class even though their economic lives are highly unstable and unsatisfactory.

If I’m concerned about my own personal satisfaction and my wife is not allowing me the personal growth I need, I may be justified in leaving. So the shift to expressive self has some positives and negatives.

It is first important to draw attention to the economic underpinnings of the old American individualism, the precise extent of which remains to be unpacked. A crude appraisal suggests that the old individualism is one of economic self-reliance achievement. If this model has largely fallen by the wayside, it is reasonable to associate this transformation, as Cherlin does, with the middle class’ growing economic security. With necessities guaranteed, more energy and attention can be devoted to examining the organization of our lives. In other words, once we secure the utilitarian, there is greater opportunity to reflect on how utilitarian arrangements express our individuality (or what we perceive as such). Interestingly, we can see the importance of legal or juridical subjectivity in guaranteeing certain human necessities and thus securing the utilitarian.

Also of interest is the transmission of this culture to the working class, formerly utilitarian through and through. If we can plausibly link the middle class’ increased opportunity for reflection on how utilitarian arrangements express individuality to stable economic conditions, such a move does not seem possible in the case of the working class. Strikingly, in face of economic and domestic uncertainty, this class has taken up for itself the same sort of discourse for which minimal economic security was thought to be an enabling precondition. The question then becomes why more energy and attention are being devoted to such examination in the absence of sufficient resources. From an economic perspective, how can there be individuality without subjectivity in the sense here?

We might think to attribute this to human nature or essence, but such an attribution would be unsound. As studies like Taylor’s have shown, human nature varies from period to period, and we cannot ascribe such qualities as expressive individuality to any fixed and permanent existence. On the contrary, this is a distinctly modern formation, one that stems from the problems and interests of post-Romantic society. Thus, we cannot simply maintain that individuality in this sense is the predominant quality over subjectivity.

Yet this line of thought does not seem entirely without merit, and it is important to attempt an explanation at why the lack of resources (to some extent secured by subjectivity in the strict sense) can likewise prompt such a response in the latter’s absence. Undoubtedly, this could be due in part to liberalism’s own shortcomings, that is, the sense that current Western governments privilege economic well-being at the expense of other forms of well-being and the general discontent that stems from this widening realization. This would, however, be shortsighted on our part to ascribe this merely to some growing malaise on the part of the governed, i.e. as a mere reaction to developments in the political sphere.

Indeed, this development within the working class highlights a striking feature of individuality that the middle class’ own changes obscure: qua formation of self, individuality does not follow from subjectivity as a consequence from its cause. (In fact, it is a priori plausible that this new growth of individuality could in turn serve to bring members of the working class together to further and cement their own status as legal subjects.) Rather, individuality is a concomitant formation of self which stands neither as antecedent nor precedent to subjectivity in the sense outlined above. The middle class’ experience with expressive individuality owes not to some essential cycle which predetermines the relation between the two.

Quite the contrary, the relationship between individuality and subjectivity observed there owes to the contingent historical conditions in which this development unfolded rather than some formal, logical or causal necessity. Individuality is latent in our age and was present for the middle class in the 1950’s as a concern in much the same way that it is now for the working class. The difference owes to the way and form in which this need makes itself felt and apparent. In short, though independent of one another, subjectivity and individuality are equally necessary and capable of unforeseen joint articulations in differing historical, economic, and social contexts.

Condensation

February 18, 2015

As vehicles for ideas, my characters might leave you with the impression that I am a creature devoid of emotion and generally incapable of bringing living characters of flesh and blood to the page. Such were my critic’s remarks: the observer incapable of breathing life into the unobservable, always looking in through the glass without a hope of understanding. Well, that critic and yourself would be wrong. It is not for a lack of human feeling, caring or empathy that my own characters, if you allow me that, are anything but. Rather, it is from too much empathy that I avoid flesh and blood, hair and bone. For to bring characters of this kind into the world be to subject them to suffering. Human characters can suffer, but ideas cannot. Certainly, Ideas can lose in luster, but they cannot suffer in any human way. In some roundabout fashion and through peopling my stories, again if you allow me that much, with ideas, I have attained the Platonic realm. My unwieldy artifice can thus be reduced to my unwillingness, my incapacity to bring into this world a being which might then suffer, a fact more revealing than I had previously realized.

PIH

February 17, 2015

It sometimes occurs to others that the characters populating my stories are mere vehicles for ideas, ideas which are, at best, half-articulated as befits a half articulate man. Tonight is one of those times, and she lays out for me in just what way these stories are neither fiction nor vignette but else, an idiot’s spittle flecking fiction’s good name.

PIG

February 16, 2015

So wrapped up in yourself, she said from a wreath of smoke, likely cigarettes, thinking on how keen an observer you are and that’s shit. You’re not far from seeing meaning in the splattered patterns of piss on the toilet bowl and that’s just one step removed from shit if you think about it. Write something with meaning.

Fr. 594

February 11, 2015

Genuine reason-giving entails a giving of words. These are not simply any words but new words to the interlocutor targeted by reason-giving. If we have previously stated that reason-giving is a means to shared expression and shared expression to shared being, and if reason-giving implies word-giving, then it follows that reason-giving is likewise a vehicle to new vocabulary, new expression and new being. For expanded vocabulary is in this way expanded being, and new words stand as so many new modes of being and understanding being. If being is indeed language, new language is, naturally, new being. Consider as cases in point the phenomena of feminism, LGBTQ and the expanding practice of suicide following its classification. This is perhaps not to suggest that we invent new words for the purpose of expanding language and being. Rather, the takeaway consists in the realization that genuine reason-giving necessitates a giving of new words.

Fr. 593

February 10, 2015

As a manner of showing the difficulty latent in self-articulation, we can engage in a series of warm-up exercises as it were. Consider for instance a situation in which we are asked to recall various memories from the recent or distant past. Ordinarily, these come simply enough. Yet the exercise becomes decidedly more complicated if a wrinkle is added to the exercise and we are asked instead to visualize these same memories from the third person perspective with ourselves as one object amongst others. With recent memories, the question arises to what degree we can assume the other position and view our person as mere object rather than embodied life.

The exercise takes a further turn when we move on to distant memories and try to recall and picture ourselves as being considerably younger. The object takes on a still stranger appearance with the attempt to fix the appearance of a different self, as it were. This apprehension meets with greater difficulty than the former to the extent that the object of apprehension is no longer that which we meet in the mirror on a daily basis. Perceiving self as object is difficult enough without the object diverging in appearance from the object as it appears under the most familiar modes of apprehension.

Thus far, attempts have been made solely at visualizing and thereby apprehending past self as object. We can add one last hurdle to the exercise by asking ourselves, once apprehended, to attribute qualities to ourselves from this observer or other position. These qualities might first be physical in kind and later emotional, mental, spiritual, etc. To what extent, even with the privileges of first-person access, however far removed, can we reliably assign ourselves quality and state at any given moment?

Although our exercise does not belong to the same modes of self-articulation and realization as those normally examined, it can perhaps be instructive to consider the ways in which this exercise illustrates pitfalls analogous to those in self-knowledge and -expression such as we encounter in a grammar of identity, the articulation of subject and individual. It is, much the same, something around which we must wrap our minds.

Follow

Get every new post delivered to your Inbox.

Join 165 other followers